Brian Stull a senior staff attorney with the Capital
Punishment Project of the American Civil Liberties Union wrote the following column on the Supreme Court's treatment of the death penalty this term for the SCOTUSBlog.
As Justice Stephen Breyer forecasted two terms ago in Glossip v.
Gross, the Supreme Court has continued its project of “patch[ing] up the
death penalty’s legal wounds one at a time.” This term, it granted relief in
three death-penalty cases, two from the nation’s leading executioner, Texas,
and one from the leader in death-row prisoners per capita, Alabama.
And it denied relief in a third Texas case (Davila v. Davis).
As these cases show, the states’ applications of the death penalty have exposed
individuals to execution who should have been protected because of their
intellectual disability (Moore v. Texas),
who were denied access to adequate tools of the defense (McWilliams
v. Dunn), and whose verdicts were infected by racial prejudice (Buck v.
Davis). The decisions granting relief are to be celebrated, but they
address only the symptoms, not the underlying problem, recognized more than 40
years ago in Furman v.
Georgia: Administration of the death penalty is inescapably arbitrary.
Intellectual disability
In Moore,
the court did what Texas advocates and developmental-disability advocates had
long asked: It struck Texas’ Briseno factors – used to exclude
intellectually-disabled prisoners from the Eighth Amendment protection against
execution, and named for State v. Briseno, in which Texas’ high criminal
court relied for its idiosyncratic definition of mental disability not on
current medical science, but on the
character Lennie in Of Mice and Men. But the court did much more than
that. It rejected other non-scientific factors often employed to deny claims of
intellectual disability under Atkins v.
Virginia, and reaffirmed that science, not stereotypes, should govern.
A diagnosis of intellectual disability requires three
things: 1) significantly subaverarge intellectual functioning (typically
measured by an IQ score roughly two standard deviations below the mean); 2) adaptive-functioning
deficits; and 3) an onset during childhood, before reaching 18. As the court
recognized three years ago in Hall v. Florida,
intellectual disability is a condition, not an IQ score, and proper diagnosis
thus places great emphasis on the second requirement, related to adaptive
functioning.
But before the ink of the 2002 Atkins decision had
dried, junk-scientific practices – unrelated to determinations of intellectual
disability in other contexts – sprang up across death-penalty states.
Before Hall, prosecution experts routinely discounted claims if the
defendant had even a single IQ score that fell above a hard cutoff of 70,
despite the countervailing views of the medical community. When considering
adaptive deficits, many state experts similarly improperly sought to exclude
defendants who had any areas of strength and contended, without medical
support, that a single area of strength outweighed the individual’s otherwise
qualifying deficits in other areas. In some cases, state experts created
“strengths” by pointing to performance in institutional (non-community)
settings, such as prison, a wholly inappropriate analysis, or argued that
deficits possibly caused by mental illness (think schizophrenia rather than
intellectual problems) should not count. The prosecution relied on these
tactics to argue for the execution of prisoners who would otherwise be deemed
intellectually disabled and courts, both in and out of Texas, adopted the
prosecutors’ arguments all too often.
In Moore, the court found an opportunity not only to
strike down the Lennie-based Briseno factors, but to condemn all of
the above practices. Writing for the court, and applying Hall’s directive
to look strictly to medical standards for determining intellectual disability,
Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg identified and rejected each of the state’s
improper practices as contrary to sound medical judgment. Her opinion should
settle many of the current arguments in pending Atkins claims, and
help to restore the protection Atkins was meant to provide in the
first instance.
Race and the death penalty
For law professors teaching federal habeas-corpus
litigation, the procedural posture of Buck reads
like a messy issue spotter. To prevail, Texas death-row prisoner Duane Buck had
to thread the needle of several doctrines, showing that: (1) A federal district
court incorrectly denied his motion, under Federal Rule of Procedure 60(b)(6),
to reopen his (previously unsuccessful) federal habeas petition attacking his
Texas death sentence; and (2) the U.S. Court of Appeals for the 5th Circuit
erroneously denied him a certificate of appealability (3) based on recent
Supreme Court decisions that would excuse a prisoner’s procedural default in
failing to raise trial counsel’s constitutionally ineffective assistance in state
post-conviction review when (4) state post-conviction counsel were themselves
ineffective in failing to raise trial counsel’s ineffectiveness.
But the heart of the case was always race and the death
penalty. Duane Buck’s death sentence was not based only on the circumstances of
his crime and life, but on his skin color as a Black man. An expert in his
case, Dr. Walter Quijano, predicted that Buck could pose a threat of future
violence if not executed because African-Americans are more likely to commit
violent crimes.
Texas had conceded constitutional error in the five other
death-penalty cases tainted by similar testimony from Quijano. But Texas sought
to defend Buck’s death sentence on the ground that in his case it was defense
counsel who introduced Quijano’s noxious testimony (even though the state
prosecutor then emphasized this testimony in summation). Writing for the court,
Chief Justice John Roberts saw no distinction, holding that Buck’s race was
improperly “put to the jury” as a basis for sentencing him to death.
The chief justice wrote, “Our law punishes people for what
they do, not who they are.” With that, threading the needle was simple. Trial
defense counsel was constitutionally ineffective for presenting Quijano’s
pernicious and prejudicial testimony. The district court should have permitted
Buck to reopen his federal habeas petition, and the 5th Circuit erred by
denying him a certificate of appealability. And, under the court’s (then new)
precedent in Trevino v.
Thaler, Buck should have been permitted to reopen his case in order to
argue that his procedural default of the trial ineffectiveness claim (in his
first state post-conviction litigation) was caused by post-conviction counsel’s
ineffective failure to argue that trial counsel had been ineffective in
presenting Quijano in the first instance. Only woefully unprepared
post-conviction counsel could have missed this claim.
Three decades ago, in McCleskey v. Kemp,
the court rejected constitutional challenges to the death penalty based on
statistical analysis showing the race of the victim to be a substantial factor
in determining which guilty offenders in Georgia are sentenced to death.
Between then and now, this study has been replicated in many
states, while Black and Latino Texas prisoners were being sentenced to
death based on Quijano’s pernicious claims, and, as the court found last term
in Foster
v. Chatman, while Black jurors were being excluded from death-penalty
trials based on racial discrimination. Because the death penalty is a
direct descendant of lynching, the taint of racial discrimination is
endemic. And the Supreme Court will continue to be called upon to cure the
incurable.
That gets us closer to the larger problem this term’s cases
reflect. The death penalty cannot be healed. McWilliams and Davila yet
again show the inadequate representation many poor people facing execution
receive – McWilliams at the trial level, where the defendant was
denied an appointed mental-health expert to aid in his defense, and Davila at
the critical level of direct appeals. The court granted relief in McWilliams.
But it denied relief in Davila – not because appellate counsel was
constitutionally effective – but because, in a 5-4 vote, it decided that a
procedurally defaulted claim of ineffective assistance of appellate counsel
could not be excused, and thereby considered in federal habeas review, due to
ineffective post-conviction counsel’s failure to raise the claim. As both cases
illustrate, across capital death-penalty jurisdictions, ineffective lawyers for
the accused have long plagued the proceedings at multiple stages: at trial, on
direct appeal, and in state post-conviction review.
Numerically, most problematic cases have come from an
earlier era. Two of the prisoners who prevailed this term were sentenced to
death before 1990 (Moore in 1980 and McWilliams in 1986) and one before 2000
(Buck in 1997). Nationally, prosecutors won 173, 301
and 265 death sentences per year in those three years.
Of the nearly 3,000 prisoners remaining on American death
rows, most come from that earlier era – a large fraction from Texas. If the
court were to look at those cases up close, as it has with the cases this term,
it would likely find the same problems of ineffective assistance, racial bias
and improper denials of Atkins claims.
Even though the same errors persist today, and new ones have
arisen, we have generally moved away from executions, imposing only 30 new
death sentences nationwide in 2016. But a handful of states still push towards executions.
They line up for the gurney increasingly geriatric prisoners, condemned in the
earlier era – including the four defendants Arkansas
rushed to execute this spring as a lethal-injection drug was expiring.
The more these old cases come to the court’s attention in coming terms, the
more likely the court will be to realize it can no longer content itself with
treating only the symptoms without confronting the larger problem.
To visit the SCOTUSBlog CLICK HERE
No comments:
Post a Comment